1 4 0 D O C . 3 1 I D E A S A N D M E T H O D S
lation shows that a light ray passing closely by a celestial body of the size of the
sun must suffer a deflection in the order of magnitude of one second of arc. It is,
after all, this result the two English expeditions confirmed last year. However, it
should be pointed out here that this simple consideration provides numerically only
half of the actual value of
deflection.[43]
This is connected to the fact that the grav-
itational field in the theory of general relativity is not represented just by a vector
field but rather by a formally more complicated structure, such that the transition
from the parallel field—that obtains in reference —to the spherically symmetric
field of a celestial body is not as simple as it might appear at first glance. This will
be clarified later.
Second, this consequence shows that the law of the constancy of the speed of
light no longer holds, according to the general theory of relativity, in spaces that
have gravitational fields. As a simple geometric consideration shows, the curvature
of light rays occurs only in spaces where the speed of light is spatially variable.
From this it follows that the entire conceptual system of the theory of special rela-
tivity can claim rigorous validity only for those space-time domains where gravita-
tional fields (under appropriately chosen coordinate systems) are absent. The
theory of special relativity, therefore, applies only to a limiting case that is nowhere
precisely realized in the real world. Nevertheless, this limiting case 〈also〉 is of fun-
damental significance for the theory of general relativity; because the fact from
which we started out, namely that no gravitational field exists in the immediate vi-
cinity of a free-falling observer, this very fact shows that in the vicinity of every
world point the results of the theory of special relativity are valid (in the infinites-
imal) for a suitably chosen local coordinate system.
This connection can be illustrated with a geometrical comparison from the the-
ory of surfaces that turned out to be of decisive significance for the 〈finding and〉
implementation of the
theory.[44]
Metric relations in the plane are described by two-
dimensional Euclidean geometry; i.e., the constructions of Euclidean geometry can
be executed by means of a compass and ruler such that a compass (set to a certain
way) plays the role of a fixed distance and the ruler that of a straight line. If one
wants to do geometry on a curved surface, e.g., on a sphere or an ellipsoid, instead
of in the plane, then there are certain laws of construction with the compass (and a
ruler osculating to the surface), but these laws are no longer expressed by those of
the Euclidean geometry of two dimensions. In its geometrical properties, a small
piece of the surface better approximates those of the plane the smaller it is 〈an in-
finitesimally small piece of the curved surface approximates in its properties, with-
out limit, those of an infinitesimal piece of the plane〉. The Euclidean 〈plane〉
geometry of two dimensions applies to constructions with a compass and ruler on
curved surfaces in infinitesimal domains. For Gaussian geometry of curved sur-
K′
[p. 26]
Previous Page Next Page